2Well-orderings and ordinals
II Logic and Set Theory
2.3 Ordinals
We have already shown that the collection of all well-orderings is a total order.
But is it a well-ordering itself? To investigate this issue further, we first define
ourselves a convenient way of talking about well-orderings.
Definition (Ordinal). An ordinal is a well-ordered set, with two regarded as
the same if they are isomorphic. We write ordinals as Greek letters α, β etc.
We would want to define ordinals as equivalence classes of well-orders under
isomorphism, but we cannot, because they do not form a set. We will provide a
formal definition of ordinals later when we study set theory.
Definition (Order type). If a well-ordering
X
has corresponding ordinal
α
, we
say X has order type α, and write otp(X) = α.
Notation. For each
k ∈ N
, we write
k
for the order type of the (unique)
well-ordering of size k. We write ω for the order type of N.
Example. In R, {2, 3, 5, 6} has order type 4. {
1
2
,
2
3
,
3
4
, ···} has order type ω.
Notation. For ordinals
α, β
, write
α ≤ β
if
X ≤ Y
for some
X
of order type
α
,
Y
of order type
β
. This does not depend on the choice of
X
and
Y
(since any
two choices must be isomorphic).
Proposition. Let
α
be an ordinal. Then the ordinals
< α
form a well-ordering
of order type α.
Notation. Write I
α
= {β : β < α}.
Proof.
Let
X
have order type
α
. The well-orderings
< X
are precisely (up to
isomorphism) the proper initial segments of
X
(by uniqueness of subset collapse).
But these are the
I
x
for all
x ∈ X
. So we can biject
X
with the well-orderings
< X by x 7→ I
x
.
Finally, we can prove that the ordinals are well-ordered.
Proposition. Let
S
be a non-empty set of ordinals. Then
S
has a least element.
Proof. Choose α ∈ S. If it is minimal, done.
If not, then
S ∩ I
α
is non-empty. But
I
α
is well-ordered. So
S ∩ I
α
has a
least element, β. Then this is a minimal element of S.
However, it would be wrong to say that the ordinals form a well-ordered set,
for the very reason that they don’t form a set.
Theorem (Burali-Forti paradox). The ordinals do not form a set.
Proof.
Suppose not. Let
X
be the set of ordinals. Then
X
is a well-ordering.
Let its order-type be
α
. Then
X
is isomorphic to
I
α
, a proper initial subset of
X. Contradiction.
Recall that we could create new well-orderings from old via adding one
element and taking unions. We can translate these into ordinal language.
Given an ordinal
α
, suppose that
X
is the corresponding well-order. Then
we define α
+
to be the order type of X
+
.
If we have a set
{α
i
:
i ∈ I}
of ordinals, we can stitch them together to form
a new well-order. In particular, we apply “nested well-orders” to the initial
segments
{I
α
i
:
i ∈ I}
. This produces an upper bound of the ordinals
α
i
. Since
the ordinals are well-ordered, we know that there is a least upper bound. We
call this the supremum of the set
{α
i
:
i ∈ I}
, written
sup{α
i
:
i ∈ I}
. In fact,
the upper bound created by nesting well-orders is the least upper bound.
Example. {2, 4, 6, 8, ···} has supremum ω.
Now we have two ways of producing ordinals: +1 and supremum.
We can generate a lot of ordinals now:
0 ω · 2 + 1 ω
2
+ 1 ω
2
· 3 ω
ω+2
ε
0
+ 1
1 ω · 2 + 2 ω
2
+ 2 ω
2
· 4
.
.
.
.
.
.
2 ω · 2 + 3 ω
2
+ 3 ω
2
· 5 ω
ω·2
ε
0
· 2
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
ω ω · 3 ω
2
+ ω ω
3
ω
ω
2
ε
2
0
ω + 1 ω · 4
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
ω + 2 ω · 5 ω
2
+ ω · 2 ω
ω
ω
ω
ω
ε
ε
0
0
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
ω + ω = ω · 2 ω · ω = ω
2
ω
2
· 2 ω
ω+1
ω
ω
.
.
.
= ε
0
ε
ε
.
.
.
0
0
= ε
1
Here we introduced a lot of different notations. For example, we wrote
ω
+ 1 to
mean
ω
+
, and
ω ·
2 =
sup{ω, ω
+ 1
, ω
+ 2
, ···}
. We will formally define these
notations later.
We have written a lot of ordinals above, some of which are really huge.
However, all the ordinals above are countable. The operations we have done so
far is adding one element and taking countable unions. So the results are all
countable. So is there an uncountable ordinal?
Theorem. There is an uncountable ordinal.
Proof.
This is easy by looking at the supremum of the set of all countable
ordinals. However, this works only if the collection of countable ordinals is a set.
Let
A
=
{R ∈ P
(
N × N
) :
R is a well-ordering of a subset of N}
. So
A ⊆
P
(
N × N
). Then
B
=
{order type of R
:
R ∈ A}
is the set of all countable
ordinals.
Let
ω
1
=
sup B
. Then
ω
1
is uncountable. Indeed, if
ω
1
were countable, then
it would be the greatest countable ordinal, but
ω
1
+ 1 is greater and is also
countable.
By definition,
ω
1
is the least uncountable ordinal, and everything in our
previous big list of ordinals is less than ω
1
.
There are two strange properties of ω
1
:
(i) ω
1
is an uncountable ordering, yet for every
x ∈ ω
1
, the set
{y
:
y < x}
is
countable.
(ii)
Every sequence in
ω
1
is bounded, since its supremum is a countable union
of countable sets, which is countable.
In general, we have the following theorem:
Theorem (Hartogs’ lemma). For any set
X
, there is an ordinal that does not
inject into X.
Proof. As before, with B = {α : α injects into X}.
Notation. Write
γ
(
X
) for the least ordinal that does not inject into
X
. e.g.
γ(ω) = ω
1
.