3 Basics of Goodwillie calculus
The calculation of the derivative will use the explicit description of PkF in the proof of its existence, which is the focus of this section.
We keep the assumptions of the previous section. To construct the universal approximation of F by a k-excisive functor, we force F to send certain strongly coCartesian diagrams to Cartesian diagrams, and it will turn out that this is enough.
More specifically, we find some strongly coCarteisan diagrams X:P(S)→C, where ∣S∣=k+1 and X(∅)=X. We then replace F(X) by lim∅=T⊆SF(X(T)) (which would equal F(X) if F were k-excisive). We repeat this procedure and hope we eventually end up with something k-excisive.
To define such an X, we need to specify X∣P=1(S), since we know X(∅)=X and everything is the left Kan extension of this. Since X is the only thing we know, the only thing we can do is to set X({s})=∗ (placing X there does no good).
We define C(−)(X):P(S)→C to be the unique strongly coCartesian diagram such that C∅(X)=X and C{s}=∗. Concretely, CT(X) is the colimit of the diagram
where the vertices are indexed by T.
We define
TkF(X)=∅=T⊆SlimF(CT(X)).
There is then a natural transformation tF:F→TkF.
Theorem
19
If F:C→D is any functor, define PkF:C→D as the sequential colimit
Then PkF is k-excisive and the natural map θF:F→PkF is the universal natural transformation to such a functor.
We first figure out what we have to prove. Of course, we have to prove that
PkF is
k-excisive. It turns out this is the only non-trivial thing to prove.
In the 1-categorical case, to prove the universal property, we first need to know that θF is an equivalence if F is already k-excisive, which is clear in our case. This means if we have a map α:F→G where G is k-excisive, then we have a diagram
Since θG is an equivalence, Pkα lifts to a map to G that makes the diagram commute.
To show that the extension to PkF is unique, suppose we have two extensions α~,α~′
Applying Pk to the whole diagram, we know that Pk(α~)∘Pk(θF)=Pk(α~′)∘Pk(θF). If Pk(θF) were an equivalence, then this implies Pk(α~)=Pk(α~′). Since Pk essentially acts as the identity on PkF and G, this implies α~=α~′.
In the ∞-categorical case, HTT 5.2.7.4 implies these two conditions are also sufficient.
As we said, the first condition is immediate from construction, and to prove that Pk(θF) is an equivalence, it suffices to show that Pk(tF:F→TkF) is an equivalence. But this is clear, since we are just shifting the sequential colimit.
So all we have to do is to show that PkF is in fact k-excisive.
Claim
Let X:P(S)→C be a strongly coCartesian k-cube. Then the canonical map θF:F(X)→(TkF)(X) factors through a Cartesian k-cube in D.
If this were true, then
PkF(X) would be the sequential colimit of Cartesian cubes, hence Cartesian (since we assumed finite limits commute with sequential colimits).
The Cartesian k-cube Y:P(S)→D we seek admits a very simple description. Indeed, we simply take F(X) and replace the ∅ vertex with the pullback of the rest of the diagram. This is then by construction a Cartesian cube, and there is a canonical map F(X)→Y by the universal property.
To show that θF factors through this map, we need to use a funny description of Y, and this description uses the fact that X is strongly coCartesian.
Fix a T⊆S. We define XT:P(S)→C by setting XT(I) to be the pushout of the diagram
where T={s1,…,sk}.
We make the following observations:
X∅(I)=X(I).
If X is strongly coCartesian, then essentially by definition, XT(I)=X(I∪T).
If we replace the bottom vertices with ∗, then this gives CT(X(I)). So there is a canonical map XT(I)→CT(X(I)).
The last fact gives us a map
F(XU(T))→F(CU(X(T)))
natural in U and T. These assemble to give maps
F(X(I))≅F(X∅(I))→∅=T⊆SlimF(XT(I))→∅=T⊆SlimF(CT(X(I)))≅TkF(X)(I)
It remains to show that the middle object is equal to Y. But it is not difficult to use the second fact to see that
∅=T⊆SlimF(XT(I))={lim∅=T⊆SF(X(T))F(X(I))I=∅I=∅.